BULLETIN
#34 Winter 2002
l RIGHTS AND
THE CONSTITUTION: THE NINTH AMENDMENT
Part 2: Treatment of Rights in the Supreme Court
l COPYRIGHTING THE LAW
#34 Winter
2002 Page 1
RIGHTS AND THE CONSTITUTION
The Ninth Amendment
Part 2: Treatment of Rights in the Supreme Court
By Stephen Plafker
In the first
part of this article, I gave a brief history of the United States
Constitution
and its Bill of Rights. I concluded: "Thus,
it is clear that the Constitution was designed to advance the sole
purpose of government: 'to secure . . . rights.' And that no rights
should be omitted "
In this part, I discuss the deterioration of the way courts have
treated rights over the years. In the third part, I show that this
deterioration was almost inevitable without a clear, logical theory
of rights and that the only solution lies in Objectivist moral
and political theory.
__________________________________ The
United States Constitution is based on a natural rights theory
of government. Under this theory, individuals have rights and governments
exist solely to protect these rights.1 In a natural rights government,
there is a law (called natural law) higher than any legislative
enactment. Any rule against this natural law is void.
This is opposed to a positive law theory under which whatever
law is enacted is proper. Under a positive law government, only
a procedural defect can invalidate a law.2
The natural
rights principle was applied in early colonial America. In 1657,
for
example, a Massachusetts judge used it to invalidate
a tax to be used to provide a home to a minister. "Such a
tax, said the magistrate, 'to take from Peter and give it to Paul,'
is against fundamental law."3 The natural rights principle
was the basis of the American Revolution. It was stated in 1761
in the famous argument of James Otis in the Writs of Assistance
Case:
As
to acts of Parliament. An act against the Constitution is void:
an act against
natural Equity is void: . . . The
Executive Courts must pass such Acts into disuse.4
In the early
years of the United States, courts commonly referred to natural
rights.5 The following, from a 1798 the Supreme
Court decision, is typical:
There are acts which the Federal, or State, Legislature cannot
do, without
exceeding their authority. There are certain vital
principles in our free
Republican governments, which will determine
and over-rule an apparent
and flagrant abuse of legislative power;
as to authorize manifest injustice by
positive law; or to take
away that security for personal liberty, or private
property, for
the protection whereof the government was established.
#34 Winter
2002 Page 2
An act of
the Legislature (for I cannot call it a law) contrary to the
great first
principles of the social compact, cannot be
considered a rightful exercise
of legislative authority.6
The question
is, what are the "great first principles of
the social compact?" No one in the early years was able to
give a definition. The best effort was made in 1823 by Bushrod
Washington, a Supreme Court justice and nephew of George Washington:
What
these fundamental principles are, it would perhaps be more tedious
than
difficult to enumerate. They may, however, be all
comprehended under the
following general heads: Protection by the
government; the enjoyment of
life and liberty, with the right to
acquire and possess property of every kind,
and to pursue and obtain
happiness and safety; subject nevertheless to such
restraints as
the government may justly prescribe for the general good of the
whole. The right of a citizen of one state to pass through, or
to reside in any
other state, for purposes of trade, agriculture,
professional pursuits, or otherwise;
to claim the writ of habeas
corpus, to institute and maintain actions of any kind
in the courts
of the state; to take, hold and dispose of property, either real
or
personal; and an exemption from higher
taxes or impositions than are paid by
the other citizens of the state; . . . to
which
may be added, the elective franchise,
as regulated and established
by the laws of the state in which it is to be exercised.7
Any theory
of rights which uses an enumeration as a definition will, in
the long term,
fail. Such a theory is in special trouble
if it includes expressions like "subject nevertheless to such
restraints as the government may justly prescribe for the general
good of the whole." The theory contains (to borrow a leftist
term) the seeds of its own destruction.
First slowly
and in small ways, then faster and in larger ways, the Supreme
Court chipped away at proper principles. In one of
the ironies of history, the elimination of slavery coincided with
an
increasing reluctance of the Supreme Court to use the language
of natural rights, especially in the economic area. An early chip
came in 1873 when the Supreme Court refused to invalidate a state-created
monopoly.8 Four years later, the Court opened the door to widespread
regulation of business:
Property does become clothed with a public interest when used
in a manner to make
it of public consequence and affect the community
at large. When, therefore, one devotes his property to a use in
which the public has an interest, he, in effect, grants to the
public an interest in that use, and must submit to be controlled
by the public for the common good, to the extent of the interest
he has thus created. He may withdraw
his grant by discontinuing
the use, but, so long as he maintains the use, he must
submit to
the control.9
In a famous case, Lochner
v. New York,10 the different attitudes
toward economic freedom were clearly stated. In a 5-4 decision,
the Court held unconstitutional a statute setting maximum hours
#34 Winter
2002 Page 3
for workers
in bakeries. The basis of the decision was that the statute was "the substantial equivalent of an enactment that
'no employee shall contract or agree to work,' more than ten hours
per day," and therefore "interferes with the right of
contract between the employer and employees," which is "part
of the liberty of the individual protected by the 14th Amendment
of the Federal Constitution." The opposite position was taken in two dissenting opinions. The
first, by Justice Harlan, stated general principles that virtually
gave the states carte blanche in economic regulation:
Regulations respecting the pursuit of a lawful trade or business
. . . are questions
for the state to determine, . . . and, unless
the regulations are so utterly unreasonable
and extravagant in
their nature and purpose that the property and personal rights
of the citizen are unnecessarily, and in a manner wholly arbitrary,
interfered with
or destroyed without due process of law, they do
not extend beyond the power
of the state to pass . . . .11
The second dissent, by Justice Holmes, was explicit in its denial
of natural economic rights:
It
is settled by various decisions of this court that state constitutions
and state
laws may regulate life in many ways
which we as legislators might think as
injudicious, or if you like
as tyrannical, as this, and which, equally with this,
interfere
with the liberty to contract. Sunday laws and
usury laws are ancient
examples. A more modern one
is the prohibition of lotteries. The liberty of the
citizen to
do as he likes so long as he does not interfere with the liberty
of others
to do the same, which has been a shibboleth for some
well-known writers, is
interfered with by school laws, by the Postoffice,
by every state or municipal
institution which takes his money for
purposes thought desirable,
whether he likes it or not.
. . . Some of these laws embody convictions or prejudices which
judges are likely
to share. Some may not. But a Constitution
is not intended to embody a particular economic
theory whether of paternalism and the organic relation of the citizen
to
the state
or of laissez faire. It is made for people of fundamentally differing
views,
and the accident of our finding certain opinions natural
and familiar, or novel,
and even shocking, ought not to conclude
our judgment upon the question
whether statutes embodying them
conflict with the Constitution of the United States.
General
propositions do not decide concrete cases. [!!] The decision
will
#34 Winter
2002 Page 4
depend on
a judgment or intuition more subtle than any articulate major
premise.12 By the time Lochner was decided, prior decisions supported the
dissenters; the majority was fighting a rear-guard battle. The
final stroke came during the New Deal period. In 1934, the Court
stated:
The court has repeatedly sustained curtailment of enjoyment of
private property
in the public interest. The owner's rights may
be subordinated to the needs of
other private owners whose pursuits
are vital to the paramount interests of
the community. The state
may control the use of property in various ways;
may prohibit advertising
billboards except of a prescribed size and location,
or their use
for certain kinds of advertising; may in certain circumstances
authorize encroachments by party walls in cities; may fix the height
of buildings,
the character of materials, and methods of construction,
the adjoining area
which must be left open, and may exclude from
residential sections offensive
trades, industries and structures
likely injuriously to affect the public health
or safety; or may
establish zones within which certain types of buildings
or
businesses are permitted and others excluded. . . .
Laws
passed for the suppression of immorality, in the interest of
health, to secure
fair trade practices, and to
safeguard the interests of depositors in banks, have
been found
consistent with due process. These measures not only affected the
use
of private property, but also interfered with the right of
private contract.
Other instances are numerous where valid regulation
has restricted the right of
contract, while less directly affecting
property rights.
The Constitution does not guarantee the unrestricted privilege
to engage in a
business or to conduct it as one pleases. Certain
kinds of business may be
prohibited; and the right to conduct a
business, or to pursue a calling, may
be conditioned. Regulation
of a business to prevent waste of the state's resources
may be
justified. And statutes prescribing the terms upon which those
conducting certain businesses may contract, or imposing terms if
they do
enter into agreements, are within the state's competency.13
Thus, virtually any economic regulation is deemed justifiable.
The deterioration
is not---cannot be---limited to property rights. Freedom of speech
and of the press inevitably follow. Since 1927,
the Federal Communications Commission has had the power to make
rules and grant and deny licenses to radio and television stations.
In doing so, it "is specifically directed to consider the
demands of the public interest in the course of granting licenses,
renewing them, and modifying them . . . . This mandate to the FCC
to assure that broadcasters operate in the public interest is a
broad one, a power 'not niggardly but expansive.'"14
Today, courts
violate property rights without blinking. In Hawaii Housing
Authority v. Midkiff15 a unanimous Supreme Court approved
a law allowing a state agency, in essence, to force an owner of "too
much" land to lease or sell it to non-owners---at a "fair" price.
Forcing Peter to sell to Paul is in fact a robbery of Peter. A
modern property owner might, at least in some respects, envy his
1657 Massachusetts predecessor.
In the third
part of this article, we will see that the failure to properly
understand rights led
#34 Winter
2002 Page 5
modern judges
to abandon the concept of natural rights entirely. And we will
discuss what is necessary to restore the concept.
__________________________________ References and Notes:
1. Ayn Rand, "The Nature of Government." Declaration
of
Independence: that to secure these rights, governments are instituted
among men . . ."
2. The English
Constitution has been said to be based on this theory: "The power and jurisdiction of parliament, says Sir
Edward Coke, is so transcendent and absolute, that it cannot be
confined, either for causes or persons, within any bounds . . .
this being the place where that absolute and despotic power, which
must in all governments reside somewhere, is entrusted by the constitution
of these kingdoms." 1 Blackstone, Commentaries on the
Laws of England 156.
3. Edward
S. Corwin, The "Higher Law" Background of
American Constitutional Law 73 (1929). This pamphlet is a reprint
of an article first published in the Harvard Law Review in 1928
and 1929.
4. Id., at
77. As John Adams said, "Then and there, the child
Independence was born."
5. For reasons that will be discussed in the third part of this
article, the courts were never consistent, in application or in
theory. Despite the deterioration in theory described in this article,
some things are now better: religious freedom for example. And
freedom of speech and press is better protected today, although
there are very ominous trends.
6. Chase, J. in Calder
v. Bull, 3 U.S. 386, 388 (1798)
7. Corfield
v. Coryell, 6 Fed.Cas. 546, 551-2 (1823). Washington is interpreting
Article
IV, § 2 of the Constitution: "The
citizens of each State shall be entitled to all privileges and
immunities of citizens in the several States." The phrase "privileges
and immunities" is a synonym for "rights." See,
Harry Binswanger, "The Constitution and States' Rights",
The Objectivist Forum, December 1987
8. Slaughter
House Cases, 16 Wall. 36 (1873)
9. Munn
v. Illinois, 94 U.S. 1 13, 126 (1877) (quoting English
authorities)
10. 198 U.S. 45 (1905)
11. 198 U.S. at 66-67, quoting from Gundling v. Chicago, 177
U.S. 183, 188
12. Id. at 75
13. Nebbia
v. New York, 291 U.S. 502, 525 - 529 (1934)
14. Red Lion Broadcasting Co. v. Federal Communications
Commission, 395 U.S. 367, 379-380 (1969) (citations omitted).
See Ayn Rand, "The Property Status of Airwaves" in Capitalism:
The Unknown Ideal.
15. 467 U.S. 229 (1984
COPYRIGHTING THE LAW
In the recent
copyright case, Veeck
v. SBCCI,1 the Fifth Circuit
Court of Appeals ruled that the author of a model code which has
been enacted into law cannot prevent its publication.
A model code is a proposed law written by a private organization.
Governments can adopt them directly or in modified form.2 SBCCI3
is a private non-profit organization in the business of drafting
model building codes for adoption by cities. SBCCI generates revenue
by selling copies of the code to the public. Copies are made available
to cities for adoption at no cost. Two towns in north Texas adopted
the code.
Peter Veeck operates a non-commercial web site that provides information
about north Texas. Veeck bought an electronic copy from SBCCI and
posted it on his Internet site. In a legal action SBCCI claimed
that Veeck was violating its copyright.
Does a model code lose its copyright protection by being enacted
into law? If so, what protection does the author have to his intellectual
property? On one hand, in order to comply with the law one must
know what the law is; a copyright is, at least partially, a restriction
of access to the law. On the other hand, the authors are entitled
to the rights of ownership---including compensation.
The court
held: "as
law, the model codes enter the public domain and are not
subject to the copyright holder's exclusive
prerogatives. As model codes, however, the organization's works
#34 Winter
2002 Page 6
retain their
protected status." The Ninth Circuit has ruled the opposite in a similar case involving
the Medicare reimbursement coding system which is copyrighted by
the AMA and must be used for all Medicare reimbursements.5
In an Objectivist
society, this issue would rarely arise. The laws involved in
these two cases, are very complex and in need
of constant updating. Most of these complex laws are non-objective.
Proper laws are usually simple and easily produced within the
government.
__________________________________
References and Notes:
1. ___ F. 3rd. ___ (5th Cir. 2002); No. 99-40632. See <sorry internet link
bad> A
two to one decision by a three judge panel was overturned by the
court 11 to 4 sitting en banc.
2. Model codes as such are common and are proper. They are often
drafted by volunteer committees and strive for completeness and
uniformity. Examples are the Model Uniform Commercial Code, the
Model Probate Code and the Model Penal Code.
3. SBCCI stands for Southern Building Code International, Inc.
and consists of 14,500 members from government bodies, the construction
industry, business and trade associations and others.
4. Veeck said his actions were motivated by a difficulty in finding
a copy of the code, but it appears that the codes were available
in the relevant city halls and from SBCCI at a reasonable cost.
Veeck's action certainly made the code easier to find.
5. Practice
Management Information Corp. v. American Medial Association,
121 F.3rd. 516, (9th Cir. 1997)
__________________________________
Copyright © 2002
The Association for Objective Law. All rights reserved. The Association
for Objective Law is a Missouri non-profit
corporation whose purpose is to advance Objectivism, the philosophy
of Ayn Rand, as the basis of a proper legal system.
|